"Our Time of Troubles... commenced with the catastrophic events of the year of 1914... Our civilization has just begun to recover." - Arnold Toynbee

Monday, November 12, 2012

Post-Modern Deconstructionism


If any fell wind of dark philosophy will winter the Christian culture of the West, it will drift for the dark towers of post-modern deconstructionist thought. Truly seductive is its grip on our world, and its sway is imperceptible because of its complexity. Michael Foucault is known as its chief architect, and below is a summary of his book Madness and Civilization, which I have written for class tonight. Here is the Mordor, the "bear and leafless day" into which I must sojourn to bring the light of God's truth to the abandoned academic halls of knowledge in the West. Though it only be autumn for the rest of civilization, my Providential journey leads through the frozen paths of "madness" in the strongholds of the Enemy. May Christ's Word be a "light to me in dark places, when all other lights go out." Pray for my courage.

P.S. Class went great tonight! My professor and classmates were dissatisfied with Foucault, and this gave me much opportunity to point out the flaws in his argumentation. While I am sure I will face much difficulty from the effects of deconstructionism in the future, as indeed we all do now that it is culture, I am ever trusting the the grace of Jesus Christ for my hope and the hope of the world, both in this Age and in the Age to Come.

Assignment V: Foucault: Madness and Civilization

Scope

Post-modern deconstructionism in Foucault's Madness and Civilization serves as a critique of the construction of ideas and interpretations in civilizational and contra-civilizational motifs. Foucault denies the essence of “terminal truths” in historical events, and moves the emphasis of historical analysis to a search for paradoxes of impressions in human perception (ix). His work seeks to describe prejudices of civilizational segregation of the insane, and inverts the conceptualizations of both Western rationality and its designated “other,” madness, in order to discover constructs of civilization within madness and madness within mainstream civilization. Only after Western civilization consciously adopted the philosophy of its own antithesis to rationality with Nietzsche and Freud was the irony of its paradox lessened but did not assure sincerity, so concludes Foucault (278, 286-289). The extent of Foucault's intellectual history of insanity encompasses not only the conceptualizations of civilization, but also of human perceptions of humanity itself, of masculinity and femininity, and of minority status.
In Faucault's estimation, from its origin, Western civilization has always framed itself against a form of contra-civilization or irrationality to its own construction of reason, and he cites the expulsion of lepers from society as an example. He argues that the Church expelled lepers from civilizational participation either through confinement or distance. Forced sea voyages represented both imprisonment and the openness of distance from social belonging. Long after leprosy declined, the rules for social expulsion remained, and as the Renaissance dawned, the category of madness grew into a place-holder for the civilizational opposite and a substitute for the imagery of death in literature and Apocalyptic iconography (6-7, 13, 16, 22-23). Here, argues Faulcault, madness entered the mainstream of ecclesiastic art in its inverse. Rather than ill preparedness for the end of the world being a sign of madness, madness served as a sign for the end of the world. Subsequently, madness infused art with “romantic identification,” a reach for human imagination outside the ordinary (17, 28-29).
The Classical Age quickly silenced the liberated voice of madness of the Renaissance by relegating madness to confinement during the middle seventeenth century. For example, Louis XIV founded the Hopital General in 1656 to confine the poor, unemployed, prisoners, and the insane (39). These undifferentiated masses were given up to sensibility in stark contrast to the privileges of Reason. According to Enlightenment diagnosis, women were most prone of hysteria of love within sensibility (45, 139-140). In accord with Catholic and Classical Western tradition, these insane were assigned to labor for moral enchantment and remedy of illness. Nevertheless, by relegating madness to the realm of the “secret,” authorities experienced the counteraction of shame for the insane which was unknown during the Renaissance, provoking an irony of regret (55, 68). Passion formed the basis for philosophical possibility of insanity, and in Diemerbroek's exploration of insanity, madness depended on melancholy. Yet underneath Diemerbroek's concept for melancholy, Foucault perceives a secret discourse of logic which connects melancholy with insane actions, such as murder. Foucault explains, “Under the chaotic and manifest delirium reigns the order of a secret delirium. In this second delirium, which is, in a sense, pure reason, reason delivered of all the external tinsel of dementia, is located the paradoxical truth of madness” (88, 96-97). In Classical interpretations of insanity, Foucault sees Pinel describing madness as a transcendence of moral nature in which the anti-nature of madness may not longer be made into unreasonableness, being interpreted within the scheme of the moral. This served as a catalyst for the psychology of the nineteenth century, whereas during the Classical age, pure physical treatment of the subject did not exist and discourses on madness divided between the “transformation of qualities” addressing madness as a phenomenon of nature and the “restitution of truth” which signified madness as unreason (197).
With the institution of asylums, confinement became more sympathetic but not liberating for insanity. Nevertheless, Faucault claims the nineteenth century asylum moved beyond absolute contradiction (as in the Age of Reason) to a form of mere minority status. Freud turned the tide by directly addressing the physician-patient paradigm, and in so doing eradicated asylum structures, madness's conceptualization of itself, and its own condemnation. Yet, Freud's diagnosis did not dispel the essential alienation of insanity; the doctor still remains in psychology a condescending and alienating figure to the estranged “subject” (252, 277-278). After Nietzsche's view of tragic art, madness artistically worked beyond its limits of danger into the realm of fulfillment, but still signaled judgment. As Foucault describes, “the moment when, together, the work of art and madness are born and fulfilled is the beginning of the time when the world finds itself arraigned by that work of art and responsible before it for what it is” (288-289).
Causation
Human subjectivity drives the formations of historical record in Foucault's deconstructionism. The initiation of ideas within certain codified systems of mores immediately begs into question the existence of counter-ideas in the irony of the opposite. In civilization, Foucault fishes out the notion of the “other,” and in this “other,” Foucault concerns himself with the constraints of the mainstream. For example, he assigns causation to passion (as a human label) in the stereotyping of madness (as a social conclusion to that label), but only within the limited perception of its period. Foucault always perceives a bitter irony in the narrowness of such perceptions: “Madness, which finds its first possibility in the phenomenon of passion, and in the deployment of that double causality which, starting from passion itself, radiates both toward the body and toward the soul, is at the same time suspension of passion, breach of causality, and dissolution of the elements of this unity” (88-91). Foucault replaces universal causation with the causations of perception, but how might post-modern criticism move past its own subjective constructs to critique the perceptions of the past in an applicable way? Foucault assumes universality in his epistemological method, but does not grant it metaphysical legitimacy.
Progress
Progress, whether civilizational or otherwise cannot stand above the dilemma of power in the self/other paradox. Social progress necessarily implies a movement upward from a “backward other,” whether it be a form of social organization or a particular sect of society, and post-modernism cannot afford to positively espouse such mobility. Yet, Foucault needs some form of liberal justice in order to discuses the confines of civilizational arraignment and responsibility (289). He implies civilizational injustice in his construct of the “other,” and so pleads for progressive reversal. The humorous irony of the implicit irony within post-modern deconstructionism is that it demands a reversal of the backward label, but it cannot do so without asking civilization to label another form of itself as backward.
Trajectory of History
History is a continuous line of impressions, in which continuity only exists within the framework of conceptualization itself. For such deconstruction, historical inquiry may only validly analyze the interpretations of source-work and not the actual events, because to do otherwise would be to assume some universal legitimacy in the source-work. History is historiography for the post-modern history.



No comments:

Post a Comment